Adjectives can also be factive or non-factive. Form sentences of the form NP be ADJ thatβ¦ (e.g. Noah is afraid thatβ¦) or it be ADJ that (e.g. it is odd thatβ¦) and decide whether they are factive or non-factive: odd, certain, sure, strange, unlikely, possible, interesting, relevant, obvious, sorry, exciting.
Section 4.3 Presupposition
What is the relationship between the sentences in (1a) and (1b)?
At first glance, we might think that this is a simple case of entailment β if it is true that Zoe is looking after Noahβs dog, then it follows that Noah has a dog. But things are more complicated. Look at the sentence in (2a):
If we were dealing with entailment, (2a), which is a negation of (1a), should be compatible both with (1b) and with its negation (2b) β in entailment, if p is false, then q can be true or false. But instead, it seems that if (1a) is false, then (1b) must still be true. In other words, (1b) is true whether (1a) is true or false:
p | q |
---|---|
T | T |
F | T |
That Noah has a dog does not logically follow from sentences (1a) and (2a) at all. Instead, it is presented as something that is taken for granted β it is presupposed.
Subsection Propositions and presuppositions
The proposition associated with q is a presupposition of the proposition associated with p (we apologize for the terminology β now you have to distinguish prepositions, propositions and presuppositions).
But how is (1b) taken for granted? Do we take the existence of entities for granted simply by mentioning them? We do not, as the following examples show:
Example (3a) does not allow us to state whether Noah has a dog or not, and (3b) clearly allows us to state that he does not have a dog. Example (3c) even claims that the entity it mentions β bad dogs β do not exist at all.
Subsection Presupposition triggers
Instead, there are specific linguistic phenomena that give rise to presuppositions (or βtriggerβ them, as philosophers say). Among these are definiteness (definite determiners, as in (4a), or possessives, like Noahβs dog) and proper names, as in (4b), all of which give rise to the presupposition that the entity referred to actually exists (this is called an existential presupposition):
Example (4a) shows that the existential presupposition is tied to the definite article: the sentence presupposes the existence of a dog, but not of a rabbit.
A second linguistic phenomenon that gives rise to presuppositions is the category of so-called factive verbs. Look at (5a) through (5d) and think about their relationship to (1b) (Noah has a dog):
Example (5a) presupposes (1b), while (5b) does not, and likewise, (5c) presupposes (1b) while (5d) does not β test this by negating the four sentences!
Verbs like know and regret are factive verbs, which means that they commit the speaker to the truth of the proposition expressed by the subordinate clause that follows, and this commitment remains even when they are negated. Other examples of factive verbs are discover, notice, realize, forget and care. In contrast, verbs like believe and report are non-factive, which means that they do not commit the speaker to the truth of the proposition expressed in the subordinate clause. Other examples of non-factive verbs are imagine, admit, claim, suggest, doubt and deny.
Question 4.3.2.
Other linguistic phenomena that trigger presuppositions are, for example, implicative verbs like manage or forget, aspectual verbs like start and stop, temporal subordinating conjunctions like before, after and since, and counterfactuals.
The presuppositions of a sentence remain constant not only when the proposition associated with that sentence is negated, but also when it is expressed as a question (as in (6a, b) or when it occurs in counterfactual sentences (as in 7a, b):
All four sentences presuppose that Noah has a dog, and both (6b) and (7b) additionally presuppose that Noah named his dog Laika.
Question 4.3.3.
Show that the entailments of a sentence do not remain constant if the sentence is negated, used as an interrogative or placed in a counterfactual context.
Subsection Cancelling presuppositions
However, while presuppositions remain constant whatever we do with a sentence, they can be cancelled by explicitly pointing out that they are false:
So, what happens to the truth of a sentence if its presuppositions are false? Philosophers of language generally agree that the truth value of such a sentence becomes indeterminate, i.e., it is neither true nor false. If Noah does not have a dog, then it is meaningless to ask whether it is true or false that Zoe watched Noahβs dog if he does not have a dog.
Linguists have a slightly different take, based on how speakers actually deal with situations where a presupposition of a sentence is false. Imagine that Zoe is falsely accused of spraying orange paint on a private airplane in order to protest against climate change. The lawyer of the airplaneβs owner asks her the following:
According to the philosophers, Zoe would have to say something like (10a) or (10b), but in fact, she is more likely to say something like (10c):
In other words, we tend to treat sentences as false if their presuppositions are false, rather than treating them as meaningless. However, this is a pragmatic strategy β strictly speaking, the philosophers are right: you cannot not regret something that you have not done, not least because you would have to not regret an infinite number of things.